miscellany (2)
blindsight and science, the “dominion clause” in Genesis, utilitarianism and deontology, and the scapegoat mechanism
ON the limits of the scientific method and the imminent paradigm shift:
Francis Bacon’s stipulation that the purview of science should prescind from a consideration of formal causality (eide, logoi)1 leads to a sort of “blindsight” amongst scientists, and by extension, most of us living today, who defer to such scientists to establish our paradigm of reality. In the same way that a person stricken with blindsight may catch a ball without being able to see it—thereby making use of his visual cortex without knowing that he is doing this—so scientific consciousness conditions us not to see the intentionality and intelligence that scientific thinking necessarily draws on for the practice of any scientific discipline. This is obvious because otherwise scientists would not know what to study to begin with, and it would be, moreover, impossible to select which parameters were relevant out of the virtual infinity of measurements that could be made on any single occasion. The result of this blindsight is that the scientific method will never be able to account for elements of reality upon which its existence is nevertheless contingent in the same way that a conclusion stands by the support of specific premises without which it would not stand. Put another way, the existence of science necessarily entails the existence of intentionality and intelligence via modus ponens. Hence, the scientific method can never deliver a science that is complete any more than an apple can fall back upward to its bough by the force of gravitation.
And God said, Let us make man in our image, after our likeness: and let them have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the earth, and over every creeping thing that creepeth upon the earth.
—Genesis 1:26 (KJV)
It is said that a book is a mirror for the soul. It is said, moreover, that for someone who lacks the ability for understanding, a book will be of no more use than is a mirror to a blindman. Concerning the notorious “dominion clause” in Genesis quoted above: people who interpret “dominion” as “domination” inadvertently reveal more about themselves than the text. They are seeing their own image in the book’s pages. “Dominion” literally means “lordship” or “rulership.” Traditionally, the hierarchy implicit in lordship entailed the obligation for stewardship and care. A father must have dominion over his young child for the latter’s sake. This hierarchical relationship is perhaps most supremely illustrated in the iconic scene following the “Last Supper” in chapter thirteen of the Gospel of John in which Jesus washes the disciples’ feet:
4 He riseth from supper, and laid aside his garments; and took a towel, and girded himself.
5 After that he poureth water into a bason, and began to wash the disciples' feet, and to wipe them with the towel wherewith he was girded.
…
12 So after he had washed their feet, and had taken his garments, and was set down again, he said unto them, Know ye what I have done to you?
13 Ye call me Master and Lord: and ye say well; for so I am.
14 If I then, your Lord and Master, have washed your feet; ye also ought to wash one another's feet.
15 For I have given you an example, that ye should do as I have done to you.
Christ came to show humanity what “lordship” or “dominion” really means. As the Master sayeth, “And he that taketh not his cross, and followeth after me, is not worthy of me.”2
Plato’s Republic dialogue explores a similar theme in one of the early exchanges in which Socrates attempts a painstaking refutation of Thrasymachus’ attempt to reduce hierarchy to oppression. As a doctor plies his art for the sake of his patient and not for his own sake, Socrates argues, so the ruler governs for the sake of his subjects. “But the doctor actually works for money and not for the sake of his patients’ health” is Thrasymachus’s rejoinder, indicating that Socrates is naïve. Certainly, a doctor might be less obliged to clock in if he were not compensated for his work, but insofar as he is allowing pecuniary considerations to inform his action, he is acting as something other than a doctor. Put another way, a doctor is only measured by his actual orientation towards the health of his patients. If there were a doctor who refrained from healing his patients out of protest or for the sake of going fishing, he would not be a doctor at all, but a protestor or a fishmonger. Similarly, the ruler who governs for anything other than the sake of his subjects and the welfare of the state is serving in an ulterior office and thus should not be regarded as a ruler altogether.
I believe that a misinterpretation of Genesis is something of a sign in the times. The difficulty that besets contemporary people when they are tasked with interpreting the “dominion clause” is likely a function of the essentially revolutionary and, to some extent, Marxist ethos of modern Liberalism. “Lordship” carries with it, in contemporary ears, the connotation of oppression, or at least, an infringement on the consent of the governed, property rights, equality, separation of church and state, individual liberty, etc. In this way, the basic philosophical and political atmosphere that we are born into and ordinarily never notice as such seems to instill in us the proclivity to interpret Genesis’ “dominion” as “domination,” which is to say, “oppression” or “subjugation.” We tend to equate liberty with license and imagine the tyrant is the only sort of king. Naturally, history has shown that not every king is not a tyrant, but to assert that the overthrow of any hierarchy to usher in the Communist utopia is no less one-sided and often leads to worse outcomes for everyone involved.
Returning to Genesis: in essence, Adam was supposed to be the priest of Creation, which is to say, the intermediary between Heaven and Earth. Christ came to accomplish what Adam failed to do and show us the true meaning of lordship. The higher and the lower are bound in a hierarchy through love. This love, when descending the hierarchy from above appears as care, responsibility, oversight, and service, and rising up the hierarchy from below as respect, submission, and loyalty.
desultory remarks on the difference between utilitarian and deontological views of ethics:
Some people say that the same action could be described in different ways according to deontology given that a given deed could be performed out of different motives. I think it would be more accurate to say that the same event could be described in different ways because the same event could actually represent entirely different actions. Si duo faciunt idem, non est idem, it is said.3 In the first case, event refers to what could be described from an external (i.e. 3rd person, or “scientific”) perspective while action implicates an agent who is performing it and hence the motive that impels it. Put another way, event could be seen as what is manifest in appearance while action includes what is not so manifest but is in fact the reason for what is manifest. Suppose I wave my hand: the event as such really only makes sense in light of the immediate inference on behalf of another that the hand-wave is more than the physical movement but is in fact a gesture. This is to say that the outer movement is an expression of an inner motive.
While I think it is fair to fault deontology for its tendency to rigidity and fundamentalism, I think utilitarianism warrants at least as much reservation given that it tries to reduce all actions to events by presupposing the generic motive of “happiness” or “pleasure.” In other words, it conceptualizes a world of outsides with no insides except insofar as the insides can serve as an occasion for the experience of pleasure to “feed the machine.” As I have indicated, I am personally opposed to the utilitarian doctrine but I hope that I can show my reasons for this judgment so that people can weigh the issue yourself and come to their own conclusions.
One more thing that I would like to add is that, essentially, these theories of ethics are attempting to define what we mean by “good” and “bad/evil.” If a person regards utilitarianism as the true theory of ethics, it just means he thinks “the action that promotes the greatest happiness for the greatest number” is an accurate paraphrasis of “good.” In other words, the terms are equivalent and could be exchanged. By the same token, there is nothing that is “good” outside of its ability to increase net happiness, according to the utilitarian doctrine. If someone is a deontologist, he will think this is wrongheaded and believe instead that an action is morally good insofar as it is performed for the right reason, irrespective of what follows from it.
***
In light of the fact that a consequentialist approach to ethics demands that our action precede our ability to evaluate it, “good” for consequentialism really means “my best guess at what is good.” In this respect, knowledge and learning becomes something like a categorical moral imperative for utilitarianism because one’s knowledge determines one’s ability to foresee the consequences of one’s deeds. Given that the ultimate measure of morality in deontology is the agent’s motive, another categorical imperative emerges. Namely, it is necessary to pay attention to one’s motives, which I think it is uncommon to do. Instead it seems that we have often already unconsciously adopted our motives before we decide to act on them.
***
I think the identification of utilitarianism with “ends-justify-the-means” thinking is very illuminating. While it may seem right to reason in this way, it is clearly a very slippery slope to Hades and I may be the last one to see the lies I am acting out by rationalizing actions through appeal to a conjectured utopia. Hitler, Stalin, and all of the psychopathically evil figures of history would have happily explained to someone why the campaigns of mass murder that they undertook were “for the greater good.”
It is tempting to say that, while utilitarianism concerns itself with outcomes, deontology also takes into account the motives for the actions which led to those outcomes. Strictly speaking, this is not correct. Instead, deontology postulates that “ethics” means “the study of duties and motives” and that it really has nothing to do with outcomes except tangentially. By analogy, some people argue that science has nothing to do with its technological implications and applications. Is there any moral component to the Manhattan Project, in which scientists were gathered in Los Alamos, NM for the purpose of inventing the atomic bomb? It is virtually certain that the CoViD-19 virus responsible for the global pandemic was engineered by scientists performing gain-of-function research in the Wuhan laboratory.4 Some people, as a result, will be liable to place the blame on science and scientists for this crisis. Others might argue that if the virus did indeed leak from this lab as the evidence suggests, it is not science to blame but politics and incentive structures. This example is intended as an analogy to illuminate that from the perspective of deontology, whatever follows from an action is irrelevant to the moral question, which is decided already in the issue of the deed according to whether it was performed for the right reason.
***
People often make statements like “someone who is loyal to utilitarian or deontological theories of ethics may end up choosing a different path when circumstances demand.” This is a very important point so I will place it in italics: how does one know just when “circumstances demand”? What is the standard that allows one to make such a judgement? The fact that one can say “sometimes we should make exceptions to one or another theory for the sake of doing the right things” begs the question by implying there is already another theory—even if it remains tacit—that could offer such guidance.
***
The “Achilles’ heal” of deontology, so to speak, is that duties are to be carried out irrespective of our personal inclinations and it is not clear how to adjudicate between two obligations if they come into conflict. Naturally, we would be disposed to appeal to our personal inclinations to settle something like this, but that is just what deontological ethics advises us against without necessarily providing us with an alternative procedure.
It might be argued that “Someone’s duty cannot override what is right or wrong.” I think I understand the sentiment behind this statement but it begs the question by presupposing that deontology is false. From the deontological perspective, someone’s duty just is to do what is right. It is not as though “right” and “wrong” are one thing and our duties are something else. Instead, our duties are a function of what is right. Our duty is to do what is right and refrain from doing what is wrong.
Neither is it adequate to appeal to consensus or “the will of the majority” to settle this issue. The idea of the majority determining what is good and right seems really arbitrary since there is nothing about being in the majority that equips a person to determine what is good or right. From the utilitarian perspective, being “good” or “right” just means “being in the majority,” in an important sense, and I think that is a corruption of meanings and it leads to a tyranny of the mob. It is an inherent problem with democracy which was recognized by the Greek philosophers and which led them to be very suspicious of this manner of organizing the state.
René Girard and the Gospels as anti-myth
René Girard (1925-2015), the anthropologist, philosopher, and social theorist who is foremost responsible for articulating a comprehensive theory of the scapegoat mechanism, started out his career believing the Gospels were myths, which, in his understanding, referred to quasi-historical accounts embellished for the sake of concealing the violence inherent at the origin of all civilizations. Over his decades of research, however, his view underwent an immense transformation and he ultimately came to see the Gospels as prophetic texts whose function was to reveal the only manner by which the scapegoat mechanism—latent everywhere—could ultimately be overcome. Namely, each of us must “take up the cross” of their own sins instead of trying to pin them on others. This is related to the two meanings of “sacrifice.” Christ transformed the function of public execution from one of propagating the mythic rites of renewal through concealment of founding violence to one of revealing the truth of scapegoating and fostering both personal responsibility and compassion for victims. The significance of this event in the history of ethics can scarcely be overestimated.
I think the example of people blaming the former President for things he could not possibly have had any influence over is a helpful one since it reveals the tendency for people to ascribe all sorts of incredible and even supernatural abilities to the victim to rationalize scapegoating him. Many people discovered a source of solidarity in their violent antipathy towards Trump. At the same time, Trump’s case is far from an ideal expression of the scapegoat phenomenon both because (1) the people were not unanimous, (2) while he was impeached and arguably slandered, many people saw this as justified, and, perhaps most importantly (3) he was not exactly a saint himself. I mention this last point because the epitome of the scapegoat would be the one who is perfectly innocent but who is indicted and sacrificed in the most violent way. Jesus of course fits this bill.
Francis Bacon (The Advancement of Learning, 1605):
Natural science...doth make inquiry, and take consideration of the same natures : but how? Only as to the Material and Efficient causes of them, and not as to the Forms...Matter rather than Forms should be the object of our attention, its configuration and changes of configuration, and simple action, and laws of action or motion, for forms are figments of the human mind, unless you call those laws of action Forms.
It is illustrative to consider Bacon’s stipulated definition of scientific inquiry to the passage from Plato’s Phaedo below, which reveals the genetic fallacy inherent in all science that proscribes its field of inquiry in this way:
As I proceeded, I found my philosopher altogether forsaking mind or any other principle of order, but having recourse to air, and ether, and water, and other eccentricities. I might compare him to a person who began by maintaining generally that mind is the cause of the actions of Socrates, but who, when he endeavoured to explain the causes of my several actions in detail, went on to show that I sit here because my body is made up of bones and muscles; and the bones, as he would say, are hard and have joints which divide them, and the muscles are elastic, and they cover the bones, which have also a covering or environment of flesh and skin which contains them; and as the bones are lifted at their joints by the contraction or relaxation of the muscles, I am able to bend my limbs, and this is why I am sitting here in a curved posture—that is what he would say, and he would have a similar explanation of my talking to you, which he would attribute to sound, and air, and hearing, and he would assign ten thousand other causes of the same sort, forgetting to mention the true cause, which is, that the Athenians have thought fit to condemn me, and accordingly I have thought it better and more right to remain here and undergo my sentence; for I am inclined to think that these muscles and bones of mine would have gone off long ago to Megara or Boeotia—by the dog they would, if they had been moved only by their own idea of what was best, and if I had not chosen the better and nobler part, instead of playing truant and running away, of enduring any punishment which the state inflicts. There is surely a strange confusion of causes and conditions in all this. It may be said, indeed, that without bones and muscles and the other parts of the body I cannot execute my purposes. But to say that I do as I do because of them, and that this is the way in which mind acts, and not from the choice of the best, is a very careless and idle mode of speaking. I wonder that they cannot distinguish the cause from the condition, which the many, feeling about in the dark, are always mistaking and misnaming.
Matthew 10:38.
“if two people do the same thing, it is not the same”
Since the beginning, the zoonotic origin hypothesis has been advanced to counter the lab-leak theory, but while the latter began, and remains entirely conjectural, each datum of evidence that has emerged in the interim has served to corroborate the lab-leak theory. Michael Schellenberger, for instance, recently disclosed that the first infections were, in fact, workers as the Wuhan Institute of Virology.
Thanks for sharing, regardless of the motive. A spark, worthy to ignite the fire of storied and wonder.
Rene' Girard's work is well descibed here, and it is helpful for me to see this so well explained. Since the body of his work, holds horrors of the lynch mob, or the seasonal angst dis-ease, of yearly personal or community grievances.
The alchemical process of cooking up one's mind, and seeking resolve through ritual or ceremony, syntax or logic, is a rather involved group of actions, whose theme lingers over every movement. Morality, whether for the community's culture, or for the legal culture of governance, can also show itself in economy of home, and relations. Industry for profit, or industry for utility.
Your mentioning of dominon, as being seen by some as domination, is poignant. Hence tyranical, authoritarian actions can appear as disharmonious, without form or righteous justice.
In the realm of governance, form takes the appearance of Law, Courts of Civil appeal for mercy or/and grace to the people's court. Here Culture meet between governance by law as compared to actual circumstance of the Cultural conditions or the economic industrial conditions. Both commerse and culture, have their mitigating circumstances, while one might expect governance to be an unbending rule of law, absent of its "spirit", law enforcement has many courts of appeal.
I write all this, simply to add an odd esoteric nuance to having "dominion" over the life in our times. Dominion, as you hinted, establishes form. HOW ONE PERFORMS STEWARDSHIP. Caretending and nurturing has more inherent patience than dictating or executing any entity that is outside our ability to order.
Within the realm of emminationist hierachies, we have the quality of wisdom ( foresight and order) as well as the consequential quality of movements. Bears don't fly. Form limits one's mastery over air, water, earth or warmth/coldness.
The mirrored book, reflects from other cultures too. Form allows Movement, according to wise functions.
Perdsian leadership, was noted as a meritocracy, where the informed and qualified are encouraged to guide or steward cultural stabilities. The old Chinese way, was for a Civil Servant to deminstrate aptitude in the "test by 10,000 questions", hence qualifing one for duties in a community, by merit of familiarity and reasoning.
How exactly we expect science to show difference to; cultural conditions, political legal conditions, or the economy of home within trade and the crafts, is a delicate art of "forming". Does the form have room for the spirit of new discoveries? Are all "movements" accounted for, by wise memory or wise expectation?